Characterizing rosy theories

Type: Article
Publication Date: 2007-09-01
Citations: 50
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1191333848

Abstract

Abstract We examine several conditions, either the existence of a rank or a particular property of þ-forking that suggest the existence of a well-behaved independence relation, and determine the consequences of each of these conditions towards the rosiness of the theory. In particular we show that the existence of an ordinal valued equivalence relation rank is a (necessary and) sufficient condition for rosiness.

Locations

  • Journal of Symbolic Logic

Similar Works

Abstract We develop a new notion of independence (ϸ-independence, read “thorn”-independence) that arises from a family of ranks suggested by Scanlon (ϸ-ranks). We prove that in a large class of … Abstract We develop a new notion of independence (ϸ-independence, read “thorn”-independence) that arises from a family of ranks suggested by Scanlon (ϸ-ranks). We prove that in a large class of theories (including simple theories and o-minimal theories) this notion has many of the properties needed for an adequate geometric structure. We prove that ϸ-independence agrees with the usual independence notions in stable, supersimple and o-minimal theories. Furthermore, we give some evidence that the equivalence between forking and ϸ-forking in simple theories might be closely related to one of the main open conjectures in simplicity theory, the stable forking conjecture. In particular, we prove that in any simple theory where the stable forking conjecture holds, ϸ-independence and forking independence agree.
Abstract We study the behaviour of stable types in rosy theories. The main technical result is that a non-þ-forking extension of an unstable type is unstable. We apply this to … Abstract We study the behaviour of stable types in rosy theories. The main technical result is that a non-þ-forking extension of an unstable type is unstable. We apply this to show that a rosy group with a þ-generic stable type is stable. In the context of super-rosy theories of finite rank we conclude that non-trivial stable types of U þ -rank 1 must arise from definable stable sets.
Just as Lascar's notion of abstract rank axiomatizes the U-rank, we propose axioms for the ranks $SU^d$ and $SU^f$, the foundation ranks of dividing and forking. We study the relationships … Just as Lascar's notion of abstract rank axiomatizes the U-rank, we propose axioms for the ranks $SU^d$ and $SU^f$, the foundation ranks of dividing and forking. We study the relationships between these axioms. As with superstable, we characterize supersimple types and theories based on the existence of these ranks. We show that the U-rank is the foundation rank of the Lascar-splitting independence relationship. We also provide an alternative definition of SUd similar to the original definition of U. Finally, we check that if in the standard characterizations of simple and supersimple we change the non-forking independence for the non-lascar-splitting independence, we characterize stable and superstable.
Abstract We develop the theory of Kim-independence in the context of NSOP $_{1}$ theories satisfying the existence axiom. We show that, in such theories, Kim-independence is transitive and that -Morley … Abstract We develop the theory of Kim-independence in the context of NSOP $_{1}$ theories satisfying the existence axiom. We show that, in such theories, Kim-independence is transitive and that -Morley sequences witness Kim-dividing. As applications, we show that, under the assumption of existence, in a low NSOP $_{1}$ theory, Shelah strong types and Lascar strong types coincide and, additionally, we introduce a notion of rank for NSOP $_{1}$ theories.
It is a well-known empirical phenomenon that natural axiomatic theories are pre-well-ordered by consistency strength. Without a precise mathematical definition of "natural," it is unclear how to study this phenomenon … It is a well-known empirical phenomenon that natural axiomatic theories are pre-well-ordered by consistency strength. Without a precise mathematical definition of "natural," it is unclear how to study this phenomenon mathematically. We will discuss the significance of this problem and survey some strategies that have recently been developed for addressing it. These strategies emphasize the role of reflection principles and ordinal analysis and draw on analogies with research in recursion theory. We will conclude with a discussion of open problems and directions for future research.
Abstract Building on Pierre Simon’s notion of distality, we introduce distality rank as a property of first-order theories and give examples for each rank m such that $1\leq m \leq … Abstract Building on Pierre Simon’s notion of distality, we introduce distality rank as a property of first-order theories and give examples for each rank m such that $1\leq m \leq \omega $ . For NIP theories, we show that distality rank is invariant under base change. We also define a generalization of type orthogonality called m -determinacy and show that theories of distality rank m require certain products to be m -determined. Furthermore, for NIP theories, this behavior characterizes m -distality. If we narrow the scope to stable theories, we observe that m -distality can be characterized by the maximum cycle size found in the forking “geometry,” so it coincides with $(m-1)$ -triviality. On a broader scale, we see that m -distality is a strengthening of Saharon Shelah’s notion of m -dependence.
We develop the theory of Kim-independence in the context of NSOP$_{1}$ theories satsifying the existence axiom. We show that, in such theories, Kim-independence is transitive and that $\ind^{K}$-Morley sequences witness … We develop the theory of Kim-independence in the context of NSOP$_{1}$ theories satsifying the existence axiom. We show that, in such theories, Kim-independence is transitive and that $\ind^{K}$-Morley sequences witness Kim-dividing. As applications, we show that, under the assumption of existence, in a low NSOP$_{1}$ theory, Shelah strong types and Lascar strong types coincide and, additionally, we introduce a notion of rank for NSOP$_{1}$ theories.
Building on Pierre Simon's notion of distality, we introduce distality rank as a property of first-order theories and give examples for each rank $m$ such that $1\leq m \leq \omega$. … Building on Pierre Simon's notion of distality, we introduce distality rank as a property of first-order theories and give examples for each rank $m$ such that $1\leq m \leq \omega$. For NIP theories, we show that distality rank is invariant under base change. We also define a generalization of type orthogonality called $m$-determinacy and show that theories of distality rank $m$ require certain products to be $m$-determined. Furthermore, for NIP theories, this behavior characterizes $m$-distality. If we narrow the scope to stable theories, we observe that $m$-distality can be characterized by the maximum cycle size found in the forking "geometry," so it coincides with $(m-1)$-triviality. On a broader scale, we see that $m$-distality is a strengthening of Saharon Shelah's notion of $m$-dependence.
Building on Pierre Simon's notion of distality, we introduce distality rank as a property of first-order theories and give examples for each rank $m$ such that $1\leq m \leq \omega$. … Building on Pierre Simon's notion of distality, we introduce distality rank as a property of first-order theories and give examples for each rank $m$ such that $1\leq m \leq \omega$. For NIP theories, we show that distality rank is invariant under base change. We also define a generalization of type orthogonality called $m$-determinacy and show that theories of distality rank $m$ require certain products to be $m$-determined. Furthermore, for NIP theories, this behavior characterizes $m$-distality. If we narrow the scope to stable theories, we observe that $m$-distality can be characterized by the maximum cycle size found in the forking geometry, so it coincides with $(m-1)$-triviality. On a broader scale, we see that $m$-distality is a strengthening of Saharon Shelah's notion of $m$-dependence.
We analyze the notion of weak elimination of hyperimaginaries (WEHI) in simple theories. A key observation in the analysis is a characterization of WEHI in terms of forking dependence -- … We analyze the notion of weak elimination of hyperimaginaries (WEHI) in simple theories. A key observation in the analysis is a characterization of WEHI in terms of forking dependence -- a condition we dub dependence-witnessed-by-imaginaries (DWIP). Generalizing results of [1] and [3], we show that in a simple theory with WEHI, forking and thorn-forking coincide. We also show that, conversely, the equivalence of independence and thorn-independence is (almost) sufficient for WEHI. Thus, the WEHI and the statement independence = thorn-independence are morally equivalent. As a further application of our technology, we demonstrate stable forking for 1-based theories of finite SU-rank that have WEHI.
In a previous paper we developed the notions of th-independence and þ-ranks which define a geometric independence relation in a class of theories which we called ``rosy''. We proved that … In a previous paper we developed the notions of th-independence and þ-ranks which define a geometric independence relation in a class of theories which we called ``rosy''. We proved that rosy theories include simple and o-minimal theories and that for any theory for which the stable forking conjecture was true, þ-forking coincides with forking independence. In this article, we continue to study properties of th-forking and find more examples of rosy theories. Among the new properties we prove in this paper are some alternative characterizations of rosy theories and some tools to prove and analyze rosiness in particular cases. Finally, we use this to find two examples of rosy non simple theories: pseudo real closed fields (PRC-fields) and the uniform companion of a large differential field defined by Marcus Tressl.
Abstract We investigate the geometry of forking for SU-rank 2 elements in supersimple ω-categorical theories and prove stable forking and some structural properties for such elements. We extend this analysis … Abstract We investigate the geometry of forking for SU-rank 2 elements in supersimple ω-categorical theories and prove stable forking and some structural properties for such elements. We extend this analysis to the case of SU-rank 3 elements.
In this paper, we introduce the notion of K-rank, where K is an strong amalgamation Fraisse class. Roughly speaking, the K-rank of a partial type is the number of "copies" … In this paper, we introduce the notion of K-rank, where K is an strong amalgamation Fraisse class. Roughly speaking, the K-rank of a partial type is the number of "copies" of K that can be "independently coded" inside of the type. We study K-rank for specific examples of K, including linear orders, equivalence relations, and graphs. We discuss the relationship of K-rank to other ranks in model theory, including dp-rank and op-dimension (a notion coined by the first author and C. D. Hill in previous work).

Cited by (40)

We present an updated exposition of the classical theory of complete first order theories without the independence property (also called NIP theories or dependent theories). We present an updated exposition of the classical theory of complete first order theories without the independence property (also called NIP theories or dependent theories).
Abstract We consider the question of when an expansion of a first-order topological structure has the property that every open set definable in the expansion is definable in the original … Abstract We consider the question of when an expansion of a first-order topological structure has the property that every open set definable in the expansion is definable in the original structure. This question has been investigated by Dolich, Miller and Steinhorn in the setting of ordered structures as part of their work on the property of having o-minimal open core. We answer the question in a fairly general setting and provide conditions which in practice are often easy to check. We give a further characterisation in the special case of an expansion by a generic predicate.
A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of … A ternary relation [Formula: see text] between subsets of the big model of a complete first-order theory T is called an independence relation if it satisfies a certain set of axioms. The primary example is forking in a simple theory, but o-minimal theories are also known to have an interesting independence relation. Our approach in this paper is to treat independence relations as mathematical objects worth studying. The main application is a better understanding of thorn-forking, which turns out to be closely related to modular pairs in the lattice of algebraically closed sets.
Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T to be “stably embedded”. Let be P with its “induced ∅-definable structure”. The conditions are … Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T to be “stably embedded”. Let be P with its “induced ∅-definable structure”. The conditions are that (or rather its theory) is “rosy”. P has NIP in T and that P is stably 1-embedded in T . This generalizes a recent result of Hasson and Onshuus [6] which deals with the case where P is o-minimal in T . Our proofs make use of the theory of strict nonforking and weight in NIP theories ([3], [10]).
The idea of applying methods and results from stability theory to unstable theories has been an important theme over the past 25 years, with o-minimality, smoothly approximable structures, and simple … The idea of applying methods and results from stability theory to unstable theories has been an important theme over the past 25 years, with o-minimality, smoothly approximable structures, and simple theories being key examples. But there have been some key recent developments which bring new ideas and techniques to the table. One of these is the investigation of abstract notions of independence, leading for example to the notions of thorn forking and rosiness. Another is the discovery that forking, weight, and related notions from stability are meaningful in dependent theories. Another is the formulation of notions of stable, compact, or more general domination, coming from the analysis of theories such as algebraically closed valued fields and o-minimal theories. The level of different approaches and techniques which end up overlapping was the reason we decided it would be a perfect time for a research meeting where the most prominent researchers would come together and discuss the ideas, results and goals that were showing up in different contexts. The dominant subjects of the meeting were the following.
Abstract Let T be a complete geometric theory and let $$T_P$$ <mml:math xmlns:mml="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML"> <mml:msub> <mml:mi>T</mml:mi> <mml:mi>P</mml:mi> </mml:msub> </mml:math> be the theory of dense pairs of models of T . We … Abstract Let T be a complete geometric theory and let $$T_P$$ <mml:math xmlns:mml="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML"> <mml:msub> <mml:mi>T</mml:mi> <mml:mi>P</mml:mi> </mml:msub> </mml:math> be the theory of dense pairs of models of T . We show that if T is superrosy with "Equation missing"<!-- image only, no MathML or LaTex -->-rank 1 then $$T_P$$ <mml:math xmlns:mml="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML"> <mml:msub> <mml:mi>T</mml:mi> <mml:mi>P</mml:mi> </mml:msub> </mml:math> is superrosy with "Equation missing"<!-- image only, no MathML or LaTex -->-rank at most $$\omega $$ <mml:math xmlns:mml="http://www.w3.org/1998/Math/MathML"> <mml:mi>ω</mml:mi> </mml:math> .
We study the notion of weak one-basedness introduced in recent work of Berenstein and Vassiliev. Our main results are that this notion characterizes linearity in the setting of geometric þ-rank … We study the notion of weak one-basedness introduced in recent work of Berenstein and Vassiliev. Our main results are that this notion characterizes linearity in the setting of geometric þ-rank 1structures and that lovely pairs of weakly one-based geometric þ-rank 1 structures are weakly one-based with respect to þ-independence. We also study geometries arising from infinite-dimensional vector spaces over division rings.
Abstract We construct a fibered dimension function in some topological differential fields. Abstract We construct a fibered dimension function in some topological differential fields.
Abstract We study the class of weakly locally modular geometric theories introduced in [4], a common generalization of the classes of linear SU-rank 1 and linear o-minimal theories. We find … Abstract We study the class of weakly locally modular geometric theories introduced in [4], a common generalization of the classes of linear SU-rank 1 and linear o-minimal theories. We find new conditions equivalent to weak local modularity: “weak one-basedness”, absence of type definable “almost quasidesigns”, and “generic linearity”. Among other things, we show that weak one-basedness is closed under reducts. We also show that the lovely pair expansion of a non-trivial weakly one-based ω -categorical geometric theory interprets an infinite vector space over a finite field.
A field K in a ring language L is finitely undecidable if Cons(Σ) is undecidable for every nonempty finite Σ⊆Th(K;L). We adapt arguments originating with Cherlin-van den Dries-Macintyre/Ershov (for PAC … A field K in a ring language L is finitely undecidable if Cons(Σ) is undecidable for every nonempty finite Σ⊆Th(K;L). We adapt arguments originating with Cherlin-van den Dries-Macintyre/Ershov (for PAC fields) and Haran (for PRC fields) to prove all PAC and PRC fields are finitely undecidable. We describe the difficulties that arise in adapting the proof to PpC fields, and show no bounded PpC field is finitely axiomatisable. This work is drawn from the author's PhD thesis [44, Chapter 4].
We introduce the concept of an amenable class of functors and define homology groups for such classes. Amenable classes of functors arise naturally in model theory from considering types of … We introduce the concept of an amenable class of functors and define homology groups for such classes. Amenable classes of functors arise naturally in model theory from considering types of independent systems of elements. Basic lemmas for computing these homology groups are established, and we discuss connections with type amalgamation properties. Mathematics Subject Classification (2010). Primary 03C45; Secondary 55N35.
The main result of this paper is that if M is a bounded PRC field then Th(M) eliminates imaginaries in the language of rings expanded by constant symbols. The main result of this paper is that if M is a bounded PRC field then Th(M) eliminates imaginaries in the language of rings expanded by constant symbols.
O-minimal structures have long been thought to occupy the base of a hierarchy of ordered structures, in analogy with the role that strongly minimal structures play with respect to stable … O-minimal structures have long been thought to occupy the base of a hierarchy of ordered structures, in analogy with the role that strongly minimal structures play with respect to stable theories. This is the first in an anticipated series of papers whose aim is the development of model theory for ordered structures of rank greater than one. A class of ordered structures to which a notion of finite rank can be assigned, the decomposable structures, is introduced here. These include all ordered structures definable (as subsets of n-tuples of the universe) in o-minimal structures. The principal result in this paper, Theorem 5.1, asserts roughly that a decomposable structure [Formula: see text] can be partitioned into finitely many definable subsets such that on each set the restriction of &lt; is a "twisted lexicographic" order. As a consequence (Corollary 5.1), for all n and linear orders ≺ definable on a subset X ⊆ M n in an o-minimal structure [Formula: see text], there is a definable partition of X such that the restriction of ≺ to each set in the partition is "lexicographic".
We show that many nice properties of a theory $T$ follow from the corresponding properties of its reducts to finite subsignatures. If $\{ T_i \}_{i \in I}$ is a directed … We show that many nice properties of a theory $T$ follow from the corresponding properties of its reducts to finite subsignatures. If $\{ T_i \}_{i \in I}$ is a directed family of conservative expansions of first-order theories and each $T_i$ is stable (respectively, simple, rosy, dependent, submodel complete, model complete, companionable), then so is the union $T := \cup_i T_i$. In most cases, (thorn)-forking in $T$ is equivalent to (thorn)-forking of algebraic closures in some $T_i$. This applies to fields with an action by $(\mathbb{Q}, +)$, whose reducts to finite subsignatures are interdefinable with the theory of fields with one automorphism. We show that the model companion $\mathbb{Q}$ACFA of this theory is strictly simple and has the same level of quantifier elimination and the same algebraic characterization of algebraic closure and forking independence as ACFA. The lattice of the fixed fields of the named automorphisms breaks supersimplicity in $\mathbb{Q}$ACFA, but away from these we find many (weakly) minimal formulas.
Higher amalgamation is a model theoretic property. It was also studied under the name generalised independence theorem. This property is defined in stable, or more generally simple or rosy theories. … Higher amalgamation is a model theoretic property. It was also studied under the name generalised independence theorem. This property is defined in stable, or more generally simple or rosy theories. In this thesis we study how higher amalgamation behaves under expansion by finite covers and algebraic covers. We first show that finite and algebraic covers are mild expansions, in the sense that they preserve many model theoretic properties and behave well when imaginaries are added to them. Then we show that in pregeometric theories higher amalgamation over ; implies higher amalgamation over parameters. We also show that in general this is not true. In fact, for any stable theory with an algebraic closed set which is not a model we construct a finite cover which fails 4-Amalgamation. With some additional assumption we can also preserve higher amalgamation over the empty set. We apply this result to abelian groups and show that (Z/4Z)ω satisfies these assumptions. Then we take the opposite direction: rather then investigating covers which have malicious properties towards amalgamation, we construct covers which will make higher amalgamation become true. First we give a new proof for the fact that there exists an algebraic cover of any stable Teq acleq(O) with higher amalgamation over O. A proof sketch of this was given by Hrushovski and a full proof appeared in an unpublished work by D. Evans. The new proof uses the notion of symmetric witness which was introduced by Goodrick, Kim and Kolesnikov. We also show with a similar approach that there exists an algebraic cover of any stable, omega-categorical theory with higher amalgamation over parameters.
Abstract We classify, in a nontrivial amenable collection of functors, all 2-chains up to the relation of having the same 1-shell boundary. In particular, we prove that in a rosy … Abstract We classify, in a nontrivial amenable collection of functors, all 2-chains up to the relation of having the same 1-shell boundary. In particular, we prove that in a rosy theory, every 1-shell of a Lascar strong type is the boundary of some 2-chain, hence making the 1st homology group trivial. We also show that, unlike in simple theories, in rosy theories there is no upper bound on the minimal lengths of 2-chains whose boundary is a 1-shell.
We consider the question of when an expansion of a topological structure has the property that every open set definable in the expansion is definable in the original structure. This … We consider the question of when an expansion of a topological structure has the property that every open set definable in the expansion is definable in the original structure. This question is related to and inspired by recent work of Dolich, Miller and Steinhorn on the property of having o-minimal open core. We answer the question in a fairly general setting and provide conditions which in practice are often easy to check. We give a further characterisation in the special case of an expansion by a generic predicate.
This paper is devoted to understand groups definable in Presburger arithmetic. We prove the following theorems: Theorem 1. Every group definable in a model of Presburger Arithmetic is abelian-by-finite. Theorem … This paper is devoted to understand groups definable in Presburger arithmetic. We prove the following theorems: Theorem 1. Every group definable in a model of Presburger Arithmetic is abelian-by-finite. Theorem 2. Every bounded group definable in a model (Z,+,<) of Presburger Arithmetic is definably isomorphic to (Z, +)^{n} mod out by a lattice.
We classify, in a non-trivial amenable collection of functors, all 2-chains up to the relation of having the same 1-shell boundary. In particular, we prove that in a rosy theory, … We classify, in a non-trivial amenable collection of functors, all 2-chains up to the relation of having the same 1-shell boundary. In particular, we prove that in a rosy theory, every 1-shell of a Lascar strong type is the boundary of some 2-chain, hence making the 1st homology group trivial. We also show that, unlike in simple theories, in rosy theories there is no upper bound on the minimal lengths of $2$-chains whose boundary is a $1$-shell.
Abstract We use axioms of abstract ternary relations to define the notion of a free amalgamation theory . These form a subclass of first-order theories, without the strict order property, … Abstract We use axioms of abstract ternary relations to define the notion of a free amalgamation theory . These form a subclass of first-order theories, without the strict order property, encompassing many prominent examples of countable structures in relational languages, in which the class of algebraically closed substructures is closed under free amalgamation. We show that any free amalgamation theory has elimination of hyperimaginaries and weak elimination of imaginaries. With this result, we use several families of well-known homogeneous structures to give new examples of rosy theories. We then prove that, for free amalgamation theories, simplicity coincides with NTP 2 and, assuming modularity, with NSOP 3 as well. We also show that any simple free amalgamation theory is 1-based. Finally, we prove a combinatorial characterization of simplicity for Fraïssé limits with free amalgamation, which provides new context for the fact that the generic K n -free graphs are SOP 3 , while the higher arity generic $K_n^r$ -free r -hypergraphs are simple.
Estudiamos las estructuras (R,+, ·, 0, 1, S), donde 2Z es el subgrupo multiplicativo de los n´umeros reales positivos que consiste en las potencias enteras de 2 y S es … Estudiamos las estructuras (R,+, ·, 0, 1, S), donde 2Z es el subgrupo multiplicativo de los n´umeros reales positivos que consiste en las potencias enteras de 2 y S es el conjunto {(et cos(t), etsen(t)) | t 2 R}, y demostraremos que no son rosaceas. En general demostraremos que cualquier expansion del cuerpo de los numeros (R,+, ·, 0, 1,
Abstract Let G be a group definable in a monster model of a rosy theory satisfying NIP. Assume that G has hereditarily finitely satisfiable generics and 1 &lt; U b … Abstract Let G be a group definable in a monster model of a rosy theory satisfying NIP. Assume that G has hereditarily finitely satisfiable generics and 1 &lt; U b ( G ) &lt; ∞. We prove that if G acts definably on a definable set of U р -rank 1, then, under some general assumption about this action, there is an infinite field interpretable in . We conclude that if G is not solvable-by-finite and it acts faithfully and definably on a definable set of U р -rank 1, then there is an infinite field interpretable in . As an immediate consequence, we get that if G has a definable subgroup H such that U р ( G ) = U р ( H ) + 1 and G /⋂ g ∈ G H g is not solvable-by-finite, then an infinite field interpretable in also exists.
Abstract We study thorn forking and rosiness in the context of continuous logic. We prove that the Urysohn sphere is rosy (with respect to finitary imaginaries), providing the first example … Abstract We study thorn forking and rosiness in the context of continuous logic. We prove that the Urysohn sphere is rosy (with respect to finitary imaginaries), providing the first example of an essentially continuous unstable theory with a nice notion of independence. In the process, we show that a real rosy theory which has weak elimination of finitary imaginaries is rosy with respect to finitary imaginaries, a fact which is new even for discrete first-order real rosy theories.

References (8)

In this paper we discuss several generalization of theorems from stability theory to simple theories. Cherlin and Hrushovski, in [2] develop a substitute for canonical bases in finite rank, ω-categorical … In this paper we discuss several generalization of theorems from stability theory to simple theories. Cherlin and Hrushovski, in [2] develop a substitute for canonical bases in finite rank, ω-categorical supersimple theories. Motivated by methods there, we prove the existence of canonical bases (in a suitable sense) for types in any simple theory. This is done in Section 2. In general these canonical bases will (as far as we know) exist only as “hyperimaginaries”, namely objects of the form a / E where a is a possibly infinite tuple and E a type-definable equivalence relation. (In the supersimple, ω-categorical case, these reduce to ordinary imaginaries.) So in Section 1 we develop the general theory of hyperimaginaries and show how first order model theory (including the theory of forking) generalises to hyperimaginaries. We go on, in Section 3 to show the existence and ubiquity of regular types in supersimple theories, ω-categorical simple structures and modularity is discussed in Section 4. It is also shown here how the general machinery of simplicity simplifies some of the general theory of smoothly approximable (or Lie-coordinatizable) structures from [2]. Throughout this paper we will work in a large, saturated model M of a complete theory T . All types, sets and sequences will have size smaller than the size of M . We will assume that the reader is familiar with the basics of forking in simple theories as laid out in [4] and [6]. For basic stability-theoretic results concerning regular types, orthogonality etc., see [1] or [9].
Abstract We develop a new notion of independence (ϸ-independence, read “thorn”-independence) that arises from a family of ranks suggested by Scanlon (ϸ-ranks). We prove that in a large class of … Abstract We develop a new notion of independence (ϸ-independence, read “thorn”-independence) that arises from a family of ranks suggested by Scanlon (ϸ-ranks). We prove that in a large class of theories (including simple theories and o-minimal theories) this notion has many of the properties needed for an adequate geometric structure. We prove that ϸ-independence agrees with the usual independence notions in stable, supersimple and o-minimal theories. Furthermore, we give some evidence that the equivalence between forking and ϸ-forking in simple theories might be closely related to one of the main open conjectures in simplicity theory, the stable forking conjecture. In particular, we prove that in any simple theory where the stable forking conjecture holds, ϸ-independence and forking independence agree.
Abstract This book gives an account of the fundamental results in geometric stability theory, a subject that has grown out of categoricity and classification theory. This approach studies the fine … Abstract This book gives an account of the fundamental results in geometric stability theory, a subject that has grown out of categoricity and classification theory. This approach studies the fine structure of models of stable theories, using the geometry of forking; this often achieves global results relevant to classification theory. Topics range from Zilber-Cherlin classification of infinite locally finite homogenous geometries, to regular types, their geometries, and their role in superstable theories. The structure and existence of definable groups is featured prominently, as is work by Hrushovski. The book is unique in the range and depth of material covered and will be invaluable to anyone interested in modern model theory.